Referencer
A Referencer is an entity that is in a reference relation with (it denotes) some referent.
- AKA: Denoter, Reference Item, Reference Entity, Referencing Entity, Designator.
- Context:
- It can typically serve as a Semantic Element in communication systems and knowledge representation.
- It can typically enable Reference Relation through designation mechanisms.
- It can typically participate in Semiotic Processes by pointing to external entities.
- It can typically function as Meaning Connector between symbols and their referents.
- It can typically contain Reference Information to facilitate referent identification.
- ...
- It can often establish Truth Conditions for propositions about referents.
- It can often operate within Linguistic Frameworks through naming conventions.
- It can often create Knowledge Connections through reference mechanisms.
- It can often facilitate Denotational Processes in formal systems.
- It can often vary in reference precision depending on contextual factors.
- ...
- It can range from being a True Referencer to being a False Referencer, depending on its referential accuracy.
- It can range from being an Entity Referencer to being a Relation Referencer, depending on its reference target.
- It can range from being an Explicit Referencer (such as an identifier) to an Implicit Referencer (such as an allusion), depending on its reference directness.
- It can range from being a Unambiguous Referencer to being an Ambiguous Referencer, depending on its referential precision.
- It can range from being a Direct Referencer to being an Indirect Referencer, depending on its reference path.
- It can range from being a Persistent Referencer to being a Temporary Referencer, depending on its temporal stability.
- It can range from being a Non-Rigid Designator to being a Rigid Designator (such as a strongly rigid designator), depending on its designation consistency.
- It can range from being a Proper Name Referencer to being a Descriptive Referencer, depending on its reference mechanism.
- ...
- It can be associated with Reference Information.
- It can be the result of a Referencing Act.
- It can operate within a Semantic System to establish meaning connections.
- It can participate in Truth-Conditional Semantics as a meaning element.
- It can be analyzed within Philosophical Frameworks of reference theory.
- It can connect Linguistic Expressions to External Realities.
- ...
- Examples:
- Referencer Types by referential mechanism, such as:
- Gestural Referencers, such as:
- Symbolic Referencers, such as:
- Identifier, such as ID=1974297622 for database entity reference.
- Unique Name for individual entity reference.
- Referencer Types by linguistic function, such as:
- Linguistic Denoters, such as:
- Content Words, such as dog, blackbird, morning star, game, large, beautiful, find, wish, brightly, luckily.
- Referencing Expressions, such as Entity Mentions.
- Definite Descriptions for specific entity reference.
- Proper Names for individual designation.
- Formal Referencers, such as:
- Linguistic Denoters, such as:
- Referencer Types by implementation domain, such as:
- Information System Referencers, such as:
- Reference Records, such as Dictionary Records or Relation Records.
- Database Keys for data entity reference.
- URIs for web resource identification.
- Cognitive Referencers, such as:
- Mental Concepts in a person's mind.
- Memory Structures for experiential reference.
- Information System Referencers, such as:
- Referencer Types by reference accuracy, such as:
- True Referencers, such as:
- False Referencers, such as:
- Referenced example: "Someone sees a woman with a man. Taking the man to be her husband, and observing his attitude to her, he says, `Her husband is kind to her.'...Suppose the man is not her husband. Suppose he is her lover, to whom she has been driven precisely by her husband's cruelty." (Kripke 1979:7)
- Mistaken Identifications due to perceptual errors.
- Referencer Types by reference target, such as:
- ...
- Referencer Types by referential mechanism, such as:
- Counter-Examples:
- Physical Particles, which are basic physical entities rather than reference relation participants.
- Physical Entities, which are referents rather than referencers.
- Pure Sensations, which lack referential intention.
- Raw Data, which requires interpretation to establish reference relations.
- Reference Relations themselves, which are relations between referencers and referents rather than being referencers.
- Referents, which are the targets of reference rather than the sources.
- See: Canonical Record, Definition, Denotation, Rigid Designator, Referent, Reference Theory, Semantic Reference, Naming, Designation, Reference Relation, Semantics, Meaning.
References
2013
- (Wikipedia, 2013) ⇒ http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/reference Retrieved:2013-12-15.
- Reference is a relation between objects in which one object designates, or acts as a means by which to connect to or link to, another object. The first object in this relation is said to refer to the second object. The second object – the one to which the first object refers – is called the referent of the first object.
The term reference is used in many spheres of human knowledge, adopting shades of meaning particular to the contexts in which it is used.
References can take on many forms, including: a thought, a sensory perception that is audible (onomatopoeia), visual (text), olfactory, or tactile, emotional state, relationship with other, [1] spacetime coordinate, symbolic or alpha-numeric, a physical object or an energy projection; but, other concrete and abstract contexts exist as methods of defining references within the scope of the various fields that require an origin, point of departure, or an original form. This includes methods that intentionally hide the reference from some observers, as in cryptography.
The following sections give specific usages of reference in different subjects.
- Reference is a relation between objects in which one object designates, or acts as a means by which to connect to or link to, another object. The first object in this relation is said to refer to the second object. The second object – the one to which the first object refers – is called the referent of the first object.
- ↑ Treanor, Brian, Aspects of alterity: Levinas, Marcel, and the contemporary debate, Fordham University Press, 2006, p.41
2009
- http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/reference/
- Reference is a relation that obtains between expressions and what speakers use expressions to talk about. When I assert ‘George W. Bush is Republican’, I use the proper name ‘George W. Bush’ to refer to a particular individual, an individual about whom I go on to speak. Although it questionable whether all words refer, there are several types of words (including proper names) which are arguably of the referring sort. These will be discussed below. The central question concerning reference is: How do words refer? What, in other words, is the “mechanism” of reference? Subsidiary questions concern the relation between reference and meaning and reference and truth. Some philosophers have thought that the nature of reference is able to shed light on important metaphysical or epistemological issues. Other philosophers are not so sanguine. Indeed, some philosophers deny that reference is a substantive relation deserving of philosophical scrutiny.
2009
- http://en.wiktionary.org/wiki/reference
- Noun
- 1. (semantics) A relation between objects in which one object designates, or acts as a means by which to connect to or link to, another object.
- …
- 5. (programming) An object containing information which refers to data stored elsewhere, as opposed to containing the data itself.
- Noun
2004
- K Bach. (2004). “Points of Reference.” In: Bezuidenhout & Reimer (eds.) 2004.
- Russell (1905) made a compelling case that descriptions, definite as well as indefinite, are devices of quantification, not referring phrases. Strawson (1950) and Donnellan (1966) pointed out that definite descriptions can be used to refer. And even indefinite descriptions can be used to refer. All this is old hat. If 'On Denoting', 'On Referring', and 'Reference and Definite Descriptions' had not provoked decades of debate, philosophers might have just thought it obvious that the mere fact that an expression can be used to refer does not show that it is inherently a referring expression, an expression that itself refers. After all, there is an obvious need for a distinction between linguistic meaning and speaker's meaning, and the distinction between linguistic reference and speaker's reference is just a special case of that (Kripke 1977, 263). Invoking this distinction does not, of course, tell us which sorts of expressions are inherently referring expressions and which are merely capable of being used to refer, but it is enough to suggest that a special reason is needed to support the claim that descriptions, which obviously can be used in nonreferring ways and which have the syntactic earmarks of quantifier phrases, nevertheless have referential readings.
2004
- M Devitt. (2004). “The Case for Referential Descriptions.” In: Bezuidenhout and Reimer (eds.) (2004). [Preprint available online]
- QUOTE: Definite descriptions (`definites') typically have the form, `the F', but may also have forms like `his F' (equivalent to `the F of him'). Indefinite descriptions (`indefinites') have the form, `a/an F'. According to Russell's theory of descriptions (1905), `the F is G' is equivalent to `there is something that is alone in being an F and it is G'; and `an F is G' is equivalent to `there is something that is an F and it is G'. So descriptions are to be understood in terms of quantifiers and the nominal `F'.
Under the influence particularly of Keith Donnellan (1966. 1968), many now think that definites are `ambiguous', having not only the `attributive' meaning captured by Russell1 but also a `referential' meaning like that of a name or demonstrative. Under the influence particularly of Charles Chastain (1975),2 some now think the same of indefinites.
- QUOTE: Definite descriptions (`definites') typically have the form, `the F', but may also have forms like `his F' (equivalent to `the F of him'). Indefinite descriptions (`indefinites') have the form, `a/an F'. According to Russell's theory of descriptions (1905), `the F is G' is equivalent to `there is something that is alone in being an F and it is G'; and `an F is G' is equivalent to `there is something that is an F and it is G'. So descriptions are to be understood in terms of quantifiers and the nominal `F'.
1994
- (Brandim, 1994) ⇒ R Brandom. (1994). “Making it Explicit. Harvard University Press.
1990
- (Fodor, 1990) ⇒ J. Fodor. (1990). “A Theory of Content and other Essays.” MIT Press.
1982
- (Evans, 1982) ⇒ Gareth Evans. (1982). “The Varieties of Reference." Oxford University Press, (published posthumously, edited by John McDowell).
1980
- (Kripke, 1980) ⇒ Saul A. Kripke. (1980). “Naming and Necessity." Harvard University Press.
1979
- (Kripke, 1979) ⇒ Saul A Kripke. (1979). “Speaker's Reference and Semantic Reference.” In: P. A. French, T. E. Uehling, Jr., and H. K. Wettstein (eds), Contemporary Perspectives in the Philosophy of Language. University of Minnesota Press, 6-27.
1972
- (Kripke, 1972) ⇒ Saul A Kripke. (1972). “Naming and Necessity.” In: "Semantics of Natural Language.” edited by D. Davidson and G. Harman. Dordrecht.
- (Donnellan, 1972) ⇒ Keith S Donnellan. (1972). “Proper Names and Identifying Descriptions.” In: D. Davidson and G. Harman (eds) The Semantics of Natural Language, Dordrecht: Reidel.
1975
- (Putnam, 1975) ⇒ Hilary Putnam. (1975). “Mind, Language, and Reality" In: Philosophical Papers, 2. Cambridge University Press.
1966
- (Donnellan, 1966) ⇒ Keith S Donnellan. (1966). “Reference and Definite Descriptions.” In: Philosophical Review, 75.
1961
- (Quine, 1961) ⇒ W. V. O. Quine. (1961). “From a Logical Point of View.” MIT Press.
1960
- (Quine, 1960) ⇒ W. V. O. Quine. (1960). “Word and Object.” MIT Press.
1950
- (Strawson, 1950) ⇒ Peter F. Strawson (1950). “On Referring.” In: Mind, 59.
- QUOTE: Referring is not something an expression does; it is something that someone can use an expression to do.
1923
- (Odgen and Richards, 1923) ⇒ Charles K. Ogden, and Ivor A. Richards. (1923). “The Meaning of Meaning: A Study of the Influence of Language upon Thought and of the Science of Symbolism." University of Cambridge.
1917
- (Russell, 1917) ⇒ Bertrand Russell. (1917) Knowledge by Acquaintance and Knowledge by Description.” In: Mysticism and Logic.
1905
- (Russell, 1905) ⇒ Bertrand Russell. (1905). “On Denoting.” In: Mind 14: 479-93.
- In the preceding chapter we saw that there are two sorts of knowledge: knowledge of things, and knowledge of truths. In this chapter we shall be concerned exclusively with knowledge of things, of which in turn we shall have to distinguish two kinds. Knowledge of things, when it is of the kind we call knowledge by acquaintance, is essentially simpler than any knowledge of truths, and logically independent of knowledge of truths, though it would be rash to assume that human beings ever, in fact, have acquaintance with things without at the same time knowing some truth about them. Knowledge of things by description, on the contrary, always involves, as we shall find in the course of the present chapter, some knowledge of truths as its source and ground. But first of all we must make dear what we mean by 'acquaintance' and what we mean by 'description'.
1892
- (Frege, 1892) ⇒ Gottlob Frege. (1892). “On Sense and Reference.” In: Zeitschrift für Philosophie und philosophische Kritik, C: 25-50.