Conscious Agent Choice
A Conscious Agent Choice is a cognitive agent action that involves a deliberate selection among conscious agent action options through conscious agent intentional processes to achieve conscious agent goals or uphold conscious agent values.
- AKA: Chosen Action, Intentional Decision, Deliberate Selection, Volitional Choice.
- Context:
- It can typically require conscious agent awareness of available conscious agent action options.
- It can typically involve conscious agent judgment about conscious agent action consequences.
- It can typically translate into concrete conscious agent action through conscious agent control.
- It can typically reflect conscious agent values and conscious agent preferences in conscious agent decision making.
- It can typically demonstrate conscious agent autonomy through conscious agent free will expression.
- It can typically embody conscious agent responsibility through conscious agent deliberate intention.
- ...
- It can often consider conscious agent external constraints and conscious agent situational factors.
- It can often balance multiple conscious agent competing interests and conscious agent objectives.
- It can often incorporate conscious agent past experience and conscious agent learned knowledge.
- It can often anticipate conscious agent future consequences and conscious agent potential outcomes.
- It can often align with conscious agent goals and conscious agent intended purpose.
- It can often entail conscious agent sacrifice of alternative possibilitys for selected option.
- It can often require conscious agent value prioritization through conscious agent deliberate weighing.
- It can often generate conscious agent psychological tension through conscious agent option evaluation.
- ...
- It can range from being a Random Conscious Agent Choice to being a Deliberate Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent decision process.
- It can range from being a Subjective Conscious Agent Choice to being an Objective Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent decision criteria.
- It can range from being a Simple Conscious Agent Choice to being a Complex Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent decision complexity.
- It can range from being an Inconsequential Conscious Agent Choice to being a Consequential Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent impact scope.
- It can range from being a Voluntary Conscious Agent Choice to being a Forced Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent freedom degree.
- It can range from being a Conscious Human Choice to being a Conscious AI Choice, depending on its conscious agent type.
- It can range from being a Malicious Conscious Agent Choice to being a Benevolent Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent moral alignment.
- It can range from being a Low-Cost Conscious Agent Choice to being a High-Sacrifice Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent choice cost.
- It can range from being an Impulsive Conscious Agent Choice to being a Reflective Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent deliberation depth.
- It can range from being a Self-Serving Conscious Agent Choice to being a Self-Transcending Conscious Agent Choice, depending on its conscious agent beneficiary scope.
- ...
- It can lead to conscious agent action consequences through conscious agent causal relations.
- It can create conscious agent responsibility through conscious agent moral agency.
- It can demonstrate conscious agent character through conscious agent choice patterns.
- It can reveal conscious agent priority through conscious agent sacrifice willingness.
- It can establish conscious agent identity through conscious agent value expression.
- It can manifest conscious agent moral courage through conscious agent principled stance.
- It can strengthen conscious agent moral muscle through conscious agent difficult decision practice.
- ...
- Examples:
- Conscious Agent Choice Types by domain, such as:
- Moral Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Ethical Conscious Agent Choice to help others despite conscious agent personal cost.
- Value-Based Conscious Agent Choice of charitable causes over personal indulgence.
- Principled Conscious Agent Choice to uphold promises despite inconvenience.
- Integrity-Based Conscious Agent Choice to tell difficult truths despite relational risk.
- Personal Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Lifestyle Conscious Agent Choices about diet and exercise with long-term health implications.
- Career Conscious Agent Choices about profession and work environment reflecting value priority.
- Relationship Conscious Agent Choices about connections and commitments involving emotional investment.
- Educational Conscious Agent Choices about learning paths requiring time dedication.
- Economic Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Purchase Conscious Agent Choices about products and services reflecting value system.
- Investment Conscious Agent Choices about resource allocation for future benefit.
- Business Conscious Agent Choices about strategy and operational approach.
- Consumption Conscious Agent Choices balancing immediate desires with ethical considerations.
- Social Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Group Participation Conscious Agent Choices about membership and involvement level.
- Social Interaction Conscious Agent Choices about engagement patterns and boundary setting.
- Community Involvement Conscious Agent Choices about contribution types and commitment degree.
- Political Participation Conscious Agent Choices expressing civic values and governance preferences.
- Moral Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Conscious Agent Choice Types by sacrifice level, such as:
- Low-Sacrifice Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Moderate-Sacrifice Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Career Path Conscious Agent Choices requiring significant investment but maintaining future flexibility.
- Relationship Conscious Agent Choices involving emotional risk but potential growth.
- Resource Allocation Conscious Agent Choices requiring current restraint for future benefit.
- High-Sacrifice Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Principled Professional Conscious Agent Choices risking career advancement for ethical stance.
- Whistleblowing Conscious Agent Choices accepting significant personal risk for moral principles.
- Caretaking Conscious Agent Choices involving major lifestyle adaptation for dependent welfare.
- Heroic Intervention Conscious Agent Choices risking personal safety for others' protection.
- Conscious Agent Choice Types by deliberation level, such as:
- Fast Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Deliberative Conscious Agent Choices, such as:
- Analytical Conscious Agent Choices involving systematic evaluation of multiple factors.
- Reflective Conscious Agent Choices examining underlying motivations and value alignment.
- Strategic Conscious Agent Choices considering long-term implications and sequential effects.
- Moral Deliberation Conscious Agent Choices weighing competing principles and ethical frameworks.
- ...
- Conscious Agent Choice Types by domain, such as:
- Counter-Examples:
- Unconscious Decisions, which lack conscious agent awareness and occur through automatic processes rather than conscious agent deliberate selection.
- Involuntary Actions, which lack conscious agent intentional control and result from biological functions rather than conscious agent choice.
- Reflexive Responses, which bypass conscious agent processing and occur as immediate reactions rather than considered selection.
- Automated Behaviors, which operate on programmed patterns without ongoing conscious agent evaluation.
- Group Decisions, which involve multiple agents collectively rather than singular conscious agent selection.
- Random Events, which lack intentional direction and occur through chance rather than conscious agent purpose.
- Coerced Actions, which override authentic preferences through external pressure rather than free conscious agent selection.
- Predetermined Outcomes, which lack genuine alternatives and reflect illusion of choice rather than actual conscious agent selection.
- See: Decision Making, Free Will, Moral Agency, Rational Choice, Conscious Action, Intentional Behavior, Agent Autonomy, Choice Architecture, Decision Theory, Behavioral Economics, Deliberate Action, Personal Sacrifice, Principled Choice, Moral Deliberation, Value Prioritization, Conscious Intention.
References
2015
- (Wikipedia, 2015) ⇒ http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/bad_faith_(existentialism)#Intentional_consciousness_and_freedom Retrieved:2015-5-22.
- For Sartre this attitude is manifestly self-deceiving. As conscious humans, we are always aware that we are more than what we are aware of, so we are not whatever we are aware of. We cannot, in this sense, be defined as our "intentional objects" of consciousness, including our restrictions imposed by (facticity) our personal history, character, bodies, or objective responsibility. Thus, as Sartre often repeated, "Human reality is what it is not, and it is not what it is." An example would be if one were now a doctor but wished and started to "transcend" to become a pig farmer. One is who one is not (a pig farmer), not who one is (a doctor): it can only define itself negatively, as "what it is not"; but this negation is simultaneously the only positive definition it can make of "what it is."
From this we are aware of a host of alternative reactions to our freedom to choose (an objective situation), since no situation can dictate a single response. Only in assuming social roles and value systems external to this nature as conscious beings can we pretend that these possibilities are denied to us; but this is itself a decision made possible by our freedom and our separation from these things. “Bad faith" is the paradoxical free decision to deny to ourselves this inescapable freedom.
- For Sartre this attitude is manifestly self-deceiving. As conscious humans, we are always aware that we are more than what we are aware of, so we are not whatever we are aware of. We cannot, in this sense, be defined as our "intentional objects" of consciousness, including our restrictions imposed by (facticity) our personal history, character, bodies, or objective responsibility. Thus, as Sartre often repeated, "Human reality is what it is not, and it is not what it is." An example would be if one were now a doctor but wished and started to "transcend" to become a pig farmer. One is who one is not (a pig farmer), not who one is (a doctor): it can only define itself negatively, as "what it is not"; but this negation is simultaneously the only positive definition it can make of "what it is."
2014
- (Wikipedia, 2014) ⇒ http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/choice Retrieved:2014-6-22.
- Choice consists of a mental decision, of judging the merits of multiple options and selecting one or more of them. While a choice can be made between imagined options ("what would I do if ...?"), often a choice is made between real options and followed by the corresponding action. For example, a route for a journey is chosen based on the preference of arriving at a given destination as soon as possible. The preferred (and therefore chosen) route is then derived from information about how long each of the possible routes take. This can be done by a route planner. If the preference is more complex, such as involving the scenery of the route, cognition and feeling are more intertwined, and the choice is less easy to delegate to a computer program or assistant.
More complex examples (often decisions that affect what a person thinks or their core beliefs) include choosing a lifestyle, religious affiliation, or political position.
Most people regard having choices as a good thing, though a severely limited or artificially restricted choice can lead to discomfort with choosing and possibly, an unsatisfactory outcome. In contrast, a choice with excessively numerous options may lead to confusion, regret of the alternatives not taken, and indifference in an unstructured existence; [1] and the illusion that choosing an object or a course leads necessarily to control of that object or course can cause psychological problems.
- Choice consists of a mental decision, of judging the merits of multiple options and selecting one or more of them. While a choice can be made between imagined options ("what would I do if ...?"), often a choice is made between real options and followed by the corresponding action. For example, a route for a journey is chosen based on the preference of arriving at a given destination as soon as possible. The preferred (and therefore chosen) route is then derived from information about how long each of the possible routes take. This can be done by a route planner. If the preference is more complex, such as involving the scenery of the route, cognition and feeling are more intertwined, and the choice is less easy to delegate to a computer program or assistant.
- ↑ Barry Schwartz, The Paradox of Choice
2013
- http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Choice
- Choice consists of the mental process of judging the merits of multiple options and selecting one or more of them. While a choice can be made between imagined options ("what would I do if ...?"), often a choice is made between real options and followed by the corresponding action. For example, a route for a journey is chosen based on the preference of arriving at a given destination as soon as possible. The preferred (and therefore chosen) route is then derived from information about how long each of the possible routes take. This can be done by a route planner. If the preference is more complex, such as involving the scenery of the route, cognition and feeling are more intertwined, and the choice is less easy to delegate to a computer program or assistant.
More complex examples (often decisions that affect what a person thinks or their core beliefs) include choosing a lifestyle, religious affiliation, or political position.
Most people regard having choices as a good thing, though a severely limited or artificially restricted choice can lead to discomfort with choosing and possibly, an unsatisfactory outcome. In contrast, a choice with excessively numerous options may lead to confusion, regret of the alternatives not taken, and indifference in an unstructured existence;[1] and the illusion that choosing an object or a course leads necessarily to control of that object or course can cause psychological problems[citation needed].
- Choice consists of the mental process of judging the merits of multiple options and selecting one or more of them. While a choice can be made between imagined options ("what would I do if ...?"), often a choice is made between real options and followed by the corresponding action. For example, a route for a journey is chosen based on the preference of arriving at a given destination as soon as possible. The preferred (and therefore chosen) route is then derived from information about how long each of the possible routes take. This can be done by a route planner. If the preference is more complex, such as involving the scenery of the route, cognition and feeling are more intertwined, and the choice is less easy to delegate to a computer program or assistant.
- ↑ Barry Schwartz, The Paradox of Choice
2011
- http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/action/
- If a person's head moves, she may or may not have moved her head, and, if she did move it, she may have actively performed the movement of her head or merely, by doing something else, caused a passive movement. And, if she performed the movement, she might have done so intentionally or not. This short array of contrasts (and others like them) has motivated questions about the nature, variety, and identity of action. Beyond the matter of her moving, when the person moves her head, she may be indicating agreement or shaking an insect off her ear. Should we think of the consequences, conventional or causal, of physical behavior as constituents of an action distinct from but ‘generated by’ the movement? Or should we think that there is a single action describable in a host of ways? Also, actions, in even the most minimal sense, seem to be essentially ‘active’. But how can we explain what this property amounts to and defend our wavering intuitions about which events fall in the category of the ‘active’ and which do not?
Donald Davidson [1980, essay 3] asserted that an action, in some basic sense, is something an agent does that was ‘intentional under some description,’ and many other philosophers have agreed with him that there is a conceptual tie between genuine action, on the one hand, and intention, on the other. However, it is tricky to explicate the purported tie between the two concepts. First, the concept of ‘intention’ has various conceptual inflections whose connections to one another are not at all easy to delineate, and there have been many attempts to map the relations between intentions for the future, acting intentionally, and acting with a certain intention. Second, the notion that human behavior is often intentional under one description but not under another is itself hard to pin down. For example, as Davidson pointed out, an agent may intentionally cause himself to trip, and the activity that caused the tripping may have been intentional under that description while, presumably, the foreseen but involuntary tripping behavior that it caused is not supposed to be intentional under any heading. Nevertheless, both the tripping and its active cause are required to make it true that the agent intentionally caused himself to trip. Both occurrences fall equally, in that sense, ‘under’ the operative description. So further clarification is called for.
There has been a notable or notorious debate about whether the agent's reasons in acting are causes of the action — a longstanding debate about the character of our common sense explanations of actions. Some philosophers have maintained that we explain why an agent acted as he did when we explicate how the agent's normative reasons rendered the action intelligible in his eyes. Others have stressed that the concept of ‘an intention with which a person acted’ has a teleological dimension that does not, in their view, reduce to the concept of ‘causal guidance by the agent's reasons.’ But the view that reason explanations are somehow causal explanations remains the dominant position. Finally, recent discussions have revived interest in important questions about the nature of intention and its distinctiveness as a mental state, and about the norms governing rational intending.
- If a person's head moves, she may or may not have moved her head, and, if she did move it, she may have actively performed the movement of her head or merely, by doing something else, caused a passive movement. And, if she performed the movement, she might have done so intentionally or not. This short array of contrasts (and others like them) has motivated questions about the nature, variety, and identity of action. Beyond the matter of her moving, when the person moves her head, she may be indicating agreement or shaking an insect off her ear. Should we think of the consequences, conventional or causal, of physical behavior as constituents of an action distinct from but ‘generated by’ the movement? Or should we think that there is a single action describable in a host of ways? Also, actions, in even the most minimal sense, seem to be essentially ‘active’. But how can we explain what this property amounts to and defend our wavering intuitions about which events fall in the category of the ‘active’ and which do not?
2005
- (Wallace, 2005) ⇒ David Foster Wallace. (2005). “Commencement Speech to Kenyon College Class of 2005."
- QUOTE: The only thing that's capital-T True is that you get to decide how you're gonna try to see it. This, I submit, is the freedom of a real education, of learning how to be well-adjusted. You get to consciously decide what has meaning and what doesn't. You get to decide what to worship.
1980
- (Davidson, 1980) ⇒ Donald Davidson. (1980). “Essays on Actions and Events." Oxford University Press.
- QUOTE: action, in some basic sense, is something an agent does that was ‘intentional under some description,’
1957
- (Anscombe, 1957) ⇒ G. E. M. Anscombe. (1957). “Intention." ISBN:978-0-674-00399-6
- http://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Intention_%28book%29 Anscombe argues that the concept of intention is central to our understanding of ourselves as rational agents. The intentions with which we act are identified by the reasons we give in answer to questions concerning why we perform actions.